Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem

Liste des GroupesRevenir à c theory 
Sujet : Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem
De : mikko.levanto (at) *nospam* iki.fi (Mikko)
Groupes : comp.theory
Date : 13. May 2025, 09:27:17
Autres entêtes
Organisation : -
Message-ID : <vvuvp5$1n44a$1@dont-email.me>
References : 1 2 3
User-Agent : Unison/2.2
On 2025-05-12 15:16:05 +0000, olcott said:

On 5/12/2025 3:53 AM, Mikko wrote:
On 2025-05-11 13:21:31 +0000, Mr Flibble said:
 
Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in
the Halting Problem
===========================================================================================   Summary
-------
Flibble argues that the Halting Problem's undecidability proof is built on
a category (type) error: it assumes a program and its own representation
(as a finite string) are interchangeable. This assumption fails under
simulating deciders, revealing a type distinction through behavioral
divergence. As such, all deciders must respect this boundary, and
diagonalization becomes ill-formed. This reframing dissolves the paradox
by making the Halting Problem itself an ill-posed question.
 1. Operational Evidence of Type Distinction
-------------------------------------------
- When a program (e.g., `DD()`) is passed to a simulating halt decider
(`HHH`), it leads to infinite recursion.
- This behavior differs from direct execution (e.g., a crash due to a
stack overflow).
- This divergence shows that the program (as code) and its representation
(as data) are operationally distinct.
- Therefore, treating them as the same "type" (as Turing's proof does)
leads to inconsistency.
 2. Generalization to All Deciders
---------------------------------
- If simulation reveals this type mismatch, then no valid decider can rely
on conflating program and representation.
- Diagonalization (e.g., defining D(x) = if H(x,x) then loop else halt)
necessarily crosses the type boundary.
- The contradiction in the Halting Problem arises from this type error,
not from inherent undecidability.
- Hence, the Halting Problem is ill-defined for self-referential input.
 3. Comparisons to Other Formal Systems
--------------------------------------
- In type-theoretic systems (like Coq or Agda), such self-reference is
disallowed:
  - Programs must be well-typed.
  - Self-referential constructs like `H(x, x)` are unrepresentable if they
would lead to paradox.
- In category theory, morphisms must respect domain/codomain boundaries:
  - Reflexive constructions require stratification to avoid logical
inconsistency.
 4. Conclusion
-------------
- The Halting Problem depends on self-reference and diagonalization.
- If these constructs are blocked due to type/category errors, the proof
breaks down.
- Thus, the Halting Problem isn’t undecidable—it’s malformed when it
crosses type boundaries.
- This is not a refutation of Turing, but a reformulation of the problem
under more disciplined typing rules.
 This model mirrors how Russell’s Paradox was avoided in modern logic: not
by solving the contradiction, but by redefining the terms that made the
contradiction possible.
 The halting problem has very simple types: the input is two strings
and the output is a bit. The same input can be given to a UTM, so
the input type of the halting problem is the input type of a UTM.
There is no divergence of behaviour: a UTM has only one behaviour for
each input and no other UTM needs be considered.
 That ignores a key fact
None of the several facts and other claims mentioned below is identifed
as a key fact.

_DDD()
[00002172] 55         push ebp      ; housekeeping
[00002173] 8bec       mov ebp,esp   ; housekeeping
[00002175] 6872210000 push 00002172 ; push DDD
[0000217a] e853f4ffff call 000015d2 ; call HHH(DDD)
[0000217f] 83c404     add esp,+04
[00002182] 5d         pop ebp
[00002183] c3         ret
Size in bytes:(0018) [00002183]
 One or more instructions of the above function
are correctly emulated by different instances of
pure x86 emulators at machine address 000015d2.
None of them is completely emulated.

None of these correctly emulated DDD instances halts.
The (correctly or othewise or not at all) emulated DDD
halts but HHH does not emulate the halting of DDD.

It is stupidly incorrect to simply assume that the
pathological relationship between HHH and DDD does
not change the behavior of DDD when it is proven
that is does change the behavior.
The pathologial relationship is there either alweys or
never. The relationship does not change. Therefore its
consequences, if any, don't change, either.
--
Mikko

Date Sujet#  Auteur
12 May 25 * Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem9Mikko
12 May 25 `* Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem8olcott
12 May 25  +* Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem5dbush
12 May 25  i`* Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem4olcott
12 May 25  i `* Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem3dbush
12 May 25  i  `* Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem2olcott
12 May 25  i   `- Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem1dbush
13 May 25  +- Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem1Richard Damon
13 May 25  `- Re: Flibble’s Leap: Why Behavioral Divergence Implies a Type Distinction in the Halting Problem1Mikko

Haut de la page

Les messages affichés proviennent d'usenet.

NewsPortal