Liste des Groupes | Revenir à theory |
On 5/1/2025 10:32 AM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:What you do not understand is that the finite string specifies the exact behaviour of the program described in the input. That behaviour does not change. That HHH cannot see that behaviour, does not change the behaviour, it is a failure of HHH. Thinking that what HHH cannot see tells something about the behaviour of the program specified in the input is an error of the programmer.Richard Heathfield <rjh@cpax.org.uk> writes:You wasted fifteen years of my life by your change-the-subject
>On 30/04/2025 19:30, Mike Terry wrote:>On 30/04/2025 16:46, Richard Heathfield wrote:>On 30/04/2025 16:15, olcott wrote:It would be (if correct) attacking the common proof for HP theorem as itOn 4/29/2025 5:03 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:>On 29/04/2025 22:38, olcott wrote:>
>
<snip>
>>>
int DD()
{
int Halt_Status = HHH(DD);
if (Halt_Status)
HERE: goto HERE;
return Halt_Status;
}
>
HHH is correct DD as non-halting BECAUSE THAT IS
WHAT THE INPUT TO HHH(DD) SPECIFIES.
You're going round the same loop again.
>
Either your HHH() is a universal termination analyser or it isn't.
The domain of HHH is DD.
Then it is attacking not the Halting Problem but the Olcott Problem,
which is of interest to nobody but you.
occurs for instance in the Linz book which PO links to from time to time.
Yes. That's what I call the Olcott Problem.
>
De gustibus non est disputandum, but I venture to suggest that (correctly)
overturning Turing's proof would be of cosmos-rocking interest to the world
of computer science, compared to which pointing out a minor flaw in a
minor[1] proof would, even if correct, have no more effect on our field
than lobbing a pebble into the swash at high tide.
>
I suspect that the only reason we bother to argue with Mr Olcott so much is
because (even if he does so unwittingly) he manages to convey the
appearance of attacking the Halting Problem, and arguing about the Halting
Problem is a lot more fun than arguing about the Olcott Problem.
>
To be of any interest, solving the Olcott Problem would have to have
important consequences. But does it? Let's see.
>
Dr Linz Theorem 12.1 (Halting Problem is Undecidable): There does not exist
any Turing machine H that behaves as required by Linz Definition 12.1. Thus
the halting problem is undecidable.
>
Dr Linz has a proof for this claim, which can be found here:
<https://john.cs.olemiss.edu/~hcc/csci311/notes/chap12/ch12.pdf>
>
If the proof is flawless, the conclusion stands and Mr Olcott is simply
wrong.
There is peculiar irony here. The proof is /not/ flawless. It has, in
fact, a flaw that PO pointed out (although in passing). PO does not
care about the flaw because it is easily fixed, but it's there none the
less[1].
>
Anyway, Linz only gives this argument because it is of historical
interest. His "real" proof immediately follows this argument (in the
book) and is a trivial corollary of the fact, proved in chapter 11, that
not all recursively enumerable languages are recursive. But no crank
ever addresses that proof. I wonder why...
>
form of rebuttal so I no longer tolerate that from an anyone.
The flaw in all of the conventional proofs is that the
mapping they they DO specify IS NOT the direct execution
of their input.
Everyone moronically ignores how the pathological relationship
between the INPUT and its TERMINATION ANALYZER CHANGES the
behavior OF THE INPUT.
*When HHH emulates DD correctly the emulated DD cannot possibly halt*
THIS IS THE BEHAVIOR OF THE FREAKING INPUT.
Les messages affichés proviennent d'usenet.