Sujet : Re: Drinker Paradox again (Re: Some Error in Dag Prawitz 1970 Paper)
De : janburse (at) *nospam* fastmail.fm (Mild Shock)
Groupes : sci.logicDate : 12. Jun 2024, 18:21:35
Autres entêtes
Message-ID : <v4cleu$1it67$1@solani.org>
References : 1 2 3
User-Agent : Mozilla/5.0 (Windows NT 10.0; Win64; x64; rv:91.0) Gecko/20100101 Firefox/91.0 SeaMonkey/2.53.18.2
Because ∃x ∀y (P(y) → P(x)) is not intuitionistically
valid, it is also the case that for a witness a
we have that ∀y (P(y) → P(a)) isn't provable.
Because otherwise the existential property would be
violated. Lets try this here:
:- show((![y]: (p(y) => p(a)))).
Fehler: Direktive fehlgeschlagen.
user auf 5
Yeah it is indeed not provable. At least when we
trust the above proof search. But its also easy
to see since ∀y and → are invertible, to prove it,
we would have to prove:
p(y) |- p(a) with y ∉ p(a)
where the side condition is from the ∀y inversion.
So the counter example is this proof:
|- ¬ ∀x ¬ ∀y (P(y) → P(x))
Mild Shock schrieb:
The counter example is a variant of the
Drinker Paradox. Its actually a horrid counter
example, since it shows something much
more disturbing. This here is
intuitionistically provable:
/* intuitionistically provable */
|- ¬ ∀x ¬ ∀y (P(y) → P(x))
But this here isn't intuitionistically
provable:
/* not intuitionistically provable */
|- ∃x ∀y (P(y) → P(x))
So the Dag Prawitz approach of modelling the
existential quantifier ∃x as ¬ ∀x ¬, which he
repeats over and over in other papers, and
in his natural deduction booklet, is a very
strong form of existential quantifier. Not the
intuitionistic existential quantifier.
Mild Shock schrieb:
The main Problem is we cannot fully identify
the existential quantifier with the negation
of the universal quantifier with a negated argument
>
in minimal and intuitionistic logic. Here some
computer experimentation. This direction
works fine, namely we have even in minimal logic:
>
1. |__∃x P(x) A
2. | |__∀x ¬P(x) A
3. | | P(a) E∃ 1
4. | | ¬P(a) E∀ 2
5. | | ⊥ E¬ 4, 3
6. | ¬ ∀x ¬P(x) I¬ 2, 5
7. ∃x P(x) → ¬ ∀x ¬P(x) I→ 1, 6
>
But the other direction doesn't work, requires
Reductio Ad Absurdum (RAA) indicated by **:
>
1. |__¬ ∀x ¬P(x) A
2. | |__¬ ∃x P(x) A
3. | | |__P(a) A
4. | | | ∃x P(x) I∃ 3
5. | | | ⊥ E¬ 2, 4
6. | | ¬P(a) I¬ 3, 5
7. | | ∀x ¬P(x) I∀ 6
8. | | ⊥ E¬ 1, 7
9. | ∃x P(x) ** RAA 2, 8
10. ¬ ∀x ¬P(x) → ∃x P(x) I→ 1, 9
>
The maximum we can do is a kind of Markov rule,
not minimal logic valid. But intuitionstic logic
valid, since it uses Ex Falso Quodlibet (EFQ)
>
indicated by *:
>
1. |__(∃x P(x) ∨ ∀x ¬P(x)) ∧ ¬ ∀x ¬P(x) A
2. | ∃x P(x) ∨ ∀x ¬P(x) E∧₁ 1
3. | ¬ ∀x ¬P(x) E∧₂ 1
4. | |__∀x ¬P(x) A
5. | | |__P(a) A
6. | | | ¬P(a) E∀ 4
7. | | | ⊥ E¬ 6, 5
8. | | ¬P(a) I¬ 5, 7
9. | | ∀x ¬P(x) I∀ 8
10. | | ⊥ E¬ 3, 9
11. | | ∃x P(x) * EFQ 10
12. | ∀x ¬P(x) → ∃x P(x) I→ 4, 11
13. | |__∃x P(x) A
14. | | P(b) E∃ 13
15. | | ∃x P(x) I∃ 14
16. | ∃x P(x) → ∃x P(x) I→ 13, 15
17. | ∃x P(x) ∨ ∀x ¬P(x) → ∃x P(x) E∨ 16, 12
18. | ∃x P(x) E→ 17, 2
19. (∃x P(x) ∨ ∀x ¬P(x)) ∧ ¬ ∀x ¬P(x) → ∃x P(x) I→ 1, 18
>
But when one proves ~ ∀x ~ A(x), this doesn't
mean one also assumes ∃x A(x) | ∀x ~A(x).
>
Mild Shock schrieb:
It seems this paper is flawed:
>
SOME RESULTS FOR INTUITIONISTIC LOGIC WITH SECOND
ORDER QUANTIFICATION RULES
Dag Prawitz - 1970
https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S0049237X08707572
>
The cut elimination might be valid.
But I guess he is jumping to conclusions
when he thinks that a proof:
>
|- ~ ∀x ~ A(x)
>
Has the existence property. The flaw
is easy to spot. He thinks that a proof,
with the non-invertible left hand ∀:
>
∀x B(x) |- C
>
Implies nevertheless a certain form of
invertibility in that there are terms
t1, .., tn such that we have a proof:
>
B(t1), ..., B(tn) |- C
>
Unless B is restricted to some special
set of formulas, I suspect that the above
is fallacious.
>
Any counter example that shows the fallacy?
>
>